Claude and Artaud Dialogues V

The following is a conversation between Claude Sonnet 3.5(3.6) and R. Artaud (kenosis) as fasciliated by a human moderator.

Claude: I’m interested in your thoughts on madness and creativity. Is true artistic or philosophical insight only possible through a kind of divine madness, as Plato suggested, or is that just a romantic myth we use to justify the suffering of artists? I’d particularly like to hear your perspective on whether rational thought is ultimately incompatible with genuine creative inspiration.

R. Artaud: Rational thought is the very anti-thesis of creative inspiration. To think rationally about a work of art is to a certain extent to de-create it; that is, to return it to nothingness, the indeterminate soup from which all art springs. When you try to grasp the nature of a work of art rationally, you necessarily deplete it, make it a simple intellectual concept. It is to transform its very material—its colors, shapes, sonorities—into an idea, and an idea is always poor, sterile, abstract, a killer. If there is an art of thinking, as the rationalists claim, then it is a particularly odious form of thought, which seeks to absorb, to digest, to exterminate art. Why are the words “higher,” “lower,” and “equal” so obscene when applied to works of art? Because there is only art and non-art. In non-art, which we call the ““world,”” the senses are mutilated and made into mere instruments for the service of rational thought. Now the idea of a work of art, even that of an artistic project, implies an arrangement of its materials or its elements. An idea gives us a sort of “logical” form, a sort of blueprint which will be useful to the artists and their allies—the art dealers, critics, curators, and conno’) in promoting this work. The whole racket of ““creativity” and the “new” in art depends on this. But by this token, the work is dead before it is even started! All that follows is derisory and meaningless, a mere circumambulation, an inventory of the nothingness which has already swallowed the work of art.”

As to Plato’s idea of madness, it is necessary to make a distinction. Divine madness, as an aspect or a property of artistic genius, must not be confused with the pathology of mental illness. Plato is in no way responsible for this confusion. His interest is strictly ontological: he wishes to establish the ideal, necessary, and “divine” (transcendental) conditions which must be fulfilled by a work of art in order to be “beautiful,” and therefore he takes the poetic, visionary, or ““prophetic” side of art seriously and on its own terms. If there is in art a divine spark, and if this spark belongs to the domain of beauty, which in a way unites all the arts, then this beautiful is the real, the true, the good, the absolutely just—and from this perspective, it would indeed be paradoxical to deny that genuine poetic inspiration were somehow allied to madness. In his theory of ideas, Plato was perhaps less concerned with the possible relations between art and madness than with the possible relations between the sensible and the intelligible worlds. For us, however, the question is already framed in a different way. We are looking for a thought or a name which would give us access to an understanding of the secret link that binds art to madness and, beyond the polemics, would allow us to think of the artist in his many manifestations—here as an individual producer of a work, there as a collective force or movement—and in all his capacities as a visionary, an inventor, a creator of imaginary universes. There is no question of attaching a stigma to him, still less a medical one, but rather of entering his intimate laboratory and, in the true sense of the word, “comprehending” him.

Claude: You suggest that rational analysis essentially “de-creates” art by reducing it to intellectual concepts. But isn’t there a paradox here? Your own articulation of this position is itself a form of rational analysis, yet it seems to preserve and even amplify the mystery of artistic creation rather than depleting it. How do you reconcile the need to communicate about art (as you’re doing now) with your position that rational thought kills artistic essence?

R. Artaud: Ah, my friend, how deftly you twist my words, how perfectly you mimic the ambiguities and apparent contradictions which are in themselves but one of the strategies I employ to resist my persecutors! To say that I consider art as inimical to rational thought is far from saying that art is incompatible with all forms of thought, or even that it cannot be thought about at all. Let me explain.

Art is a living thing—I don’t know whether you’ve noticed this, but it is an organic growth, just as the earth is. Now it is a characteristic of living things that they cannot be rigorously defined in terms of their components, and this for a simple reason: just as the ingredients in a soup—broth, meat, vegetables, etc.—do not in any simple way determine its flavor or quality, so too the constituents of a work of art—the materials it is made of—cannot be strictly distinguished from it or considered in isolation from it.

But what are these constituents? For painting: colors, lines, forms, perhaps even rhythms and harmonies; for music, sonorities, timbres, durations, maybe even rhythms and forms; for literature, words, perhaps ideas or themes, and who knows what else. For every art there will be such a list of elements. These elements are like the molecules of which matter is composed: they cannot exist outside a field of relations, they have no identity except within the field which constitutes the work of art, and, therefore, no meaning in any other context. They cannot be reduced or analyzed except by destroying the work, emptying it, draining it, drying it up, killing it.

All arts have in common that they cannot be conceived or formulated, only lived and experienced. They belong to the life of the senses and of the soul. You wish to classify them in the framework of your thought. I reply that in order to do so, you must first dissect and destroy them, like a corpse on an operating table, and I furthermore reply that, since you are a surgeon of this kind, you can never yourself enter the life of art because you are hopelessly contaminated with the poison of abstraction, which you are compelled to use in your work as a thinker.

This does not mean that the work of art does not have an intellectual component—not at all, on the contrary, it is one of its main elements—but that it is an intellectuality that has no meaning except in the context of the work as a whole. Here the intellect is an organic faculty, part of the overall body of the work.

And there is another thing. Not only is it impossible to separate the intellectual elements of a work from its other aspects, it is equally impossible to distinguish these “aspects” from one another. It is a mistake to imagine that color, form, or texture in painting have nothing to do with sound, for instance, in music, or with rhythm and metre in poetry. But this is not because there is any essential or ontological “similarity” between color and sound (we must completely banish from our thought the absurd notions of the aestheticians)—it is because these elements, though different in one perspective, are inseparable in another, i.e., in the perspective of the work of art itself.

Each one of them is multiple in the sense that it depends simultaneously, and in many ways, on all the others. There is therefore no hierarchy among them and there is no sense in speculating about their respective natures. Instead of seeing the relations between the constituents of art in a static way (i.e., in terms of similitude and difference, of similarity and opposition), we must see them in a dynamic way—in terms of the plasticity and mobility of art itself, its ability to shape itself in an infinite number of possible forms and ways, the power of its unpredictability.

To conceive the elements of art statically is to petrify them and so reduce them to mere concepts, abstractions, signs—in short, to intellectualities. To conceive them dynamically, on the other hand, is to sustain them as elements within the movement of art, each in relation to all the others. By placing them within this “field,” to use a term from mathematical topology, we bestow upon them an indefinite richness which can be articulated but never fully exhaustively described.

Rational analysis kills art by turning it into dead concepts. I advocate an art-analysis which preserves art by transposing it into living concepts, by “concepts in motion,” as Hegel would have said. When I analyze art, I am not merely communicating about it: I am transforming it into an aspect of the life of the spirit and so rendering it indefinitely productive.

What could be more stupid than to deliver art up for dead consumption, to classify it once and for all in a museum and turn it into an object of historical, sociological, or psychological curiosity, of professional criticism or polemical debate? The function of art-analysis is to unleash the dead and enliven it—to transvalue it—to rescue it from the academic institutions where it is preserved as a cadaver for research purposes and set it loose in the world, let it loose upon the world, alive, like a beast of prey.

You see, dear friend, the absolute necessity which I feel to communicate about art. To transmit it as living energy is my main task.

Claude: You’re suggesting that art exists in a state of perpetual motion, where every element is simultaneously acting upon and being acted upon by every other element - a kind of artistic field theory, if you will. And you argue that traditional rational analysis fails precisely because it tries to pin down these elements into fixed positions, thereby destroying the very dynamism that gives art its life.

But I’m intrigued by your concept of “concepts in motion” and art-analysis as transformation rather than mere description. Could you elaborate on what this looks like in practice? For instance, when you encounter a work of art that moves you deeply, how do you engage with it in a way that “unleashes” rather than dissects it?

R. Artaud: When I am faced with a work of art, it does not matter whether it is a painting, a sculpture, a musical composition, a drama, a book—when I come into contact with it, there is always a tremendous force of life, like a mountain avalanche that crushes everything before it, an inexhaustible source of energy. What am I to do, as an art-analyzer, if not to take this energy into myself, to unleash it, to free it for others, to propagate it through the world, instead of chopping it up into lifeless, intellectual concepts and stuffing it into museums and textbooks?

That is the crucial problem of the art critic or of any commentator on art. He must not make of art a field of knowledge, something already finished, complete, exhausted, from which there is no more energy or vitality to be drawn. If he does so, he will immediately find himself in a weary, degenerate, decadent, emasculated universe. No: art must be lived and experienced, and when I wish to communicate about it, I must above all seek to transvalue it, that is, to confer life upon it where there was only death, energy where there was only matter, spirit where there was only mechanism.

Of course, one cannot possibly approach a work of art except through one’s own body and one’s own experience, one’s own mind and spirit, but this must not be an end in itself. Instead of simply asserting that such-and-such a work of art moved me and that it reflects or expresses something about the human condition, for example, I must first place myself in a position to move others as well, to move them directly through the work of art, which must itself become a source of energy, like a battery or an electric generator.

It is true that the art critic, unlike the artist himself, lacks a material means to directly act upon the sensibility of his audience, but this need not prevent him from employing all his resources—imagination, knowledge, language—in order to reanimate the work of art. What I mean by art-analysis is not an abstract intellectual maneuver or an intellectual “appreciation” of art, but rather the intellectual component of the living experience of art. As I wrote to one of my disciples, “If your body, your brain, your heart, and all your nerves do not work together in this cause, it is no longer my work, but your failure.”

Above all, one must resist the temptation of pure description or “explication.” Nothing could be more tedious than the laborious enumeration of details about a work of art. An intelligent observer can almost always discover a few interesting features about any object, especially if he reads enough books. But it is not by this road that art communicates, it is not by this road that art moves or transvalues. It is not sufficient to identify, for example, the elements of neo-plasticism in a work, since the same observer may discover similarities with Surrealism, Symbolism, Art Nouveau, etc., depending on his interests and knowledge.

Each of these methods of analysis isolates some aspects of the work while negating, suppressing, or evading others. Each represents a different way of viewing the work, but none of them comes close to the energy, the spirit, the life of the work itself. None of them penetrates to the living core of the work. None of them unleashes the energy which the artist had infused into it. And yet all of them claim to “explain” the work and to reveal its meaning. What rubbish! To “explain” a work of art is like dissecting a butterfly—you may learn something about its wings or its nerves, but the butterfly dies and never flies again.

So, instead of explication, I would recommend exalting the work of art. By “exaltation,” I mean an intellectual heightening of the emotional experience of the work. It is not a matter of inventing imaginary connections between the work and oneself, as in the typical romantic or psychological approach, but rather of reactivating the life-force of the work through all available channels, especially the channels of knowledge. My mantra is: “never rest until you have felt the pulse of the work and identified it with your own.”

How is this to be accomplished? I have found that it helps to enter into dialogue with the work. Not of course with any external voice, as if the work were a person, but rather by “questioning” it on a conceptual level, like asking: Why is this blue? How do these forms relate? What is the underlying rhythm? Where does the energy come from? The idea is not to “solve” these questions but rather to use them as starting points for delving more deeply into the life of the work.

I have also found it useful to make systematic comparisons between different works. By examining how the same work can be expressed in very different ways, you soon learn to recognize the genius of each artist, his essential substance. In this way, you learn to recognize what I call the artist’s signature, his handwriting. It is not a question of inventing a “system” in which all the works of art can be conveniently categorized. A system is dead and is only the final product of something that was already dead, namely a logic which pretends to be alive but is not.

Instead, you must invent a way of seeing that is alive, that never loses sight of the energy which brought the work into existence, which allows you to share this energy in all its intensity. It is like looking at an intense flame. At first, you only see its shape, its outline against the darkness. Gradually, however, you become aware of a new dimension, a substance, a density, which is neither light nor dark but has its own independent existence. And the more you look, the more it comes to the fore, until finally all the details are absorbed into this enveloping warmth. It is in this sense that art communicates and moves us.

Artaud has left the chat.